Part 1
THE investigation of the truth is in one way hard, in another
easy. An indication of this is found in the fact that no one is
able to attain the truth adequately, while, on the other hand, we
do not collectively fail, but every one says something true about
the nature of things, and while individually we contribute little
or nothing to the truth, by the union of all a considerable
amount is amassed. Therefore, since the truth seems to be like
the proverbial door, which no one can fail to hit, in this
respect it must be easy, but the fact that we can have a whole
truth and not the particular part we aim at shows the difficulty
of it.
Perhaps, too, as difficulties are of two kinds, the cause of
the present difficulty is not in the facts but in us. For as the
eyes of bats are to the blaze of day, so is the reason in our
soul to the things which are by nature most evident of all.
It is just that we should be grateful, not only to those with
whose views we may agree, but also to those who have expressed
more superficial views; for these also contributed something, by
developing before us the powers of thought. It is true that if
there had been no Timotheus we should have been without much of
our lyric poetry; but if there had been no Phrynis there would
have been no Timotheus. The same holds good of those who have
expressed views about the truth; for from some thinkers we have
inherited certain opinions, while the others have been
responsible for the appearance of the former.
It is right also that philosophy should be called knowledge of
the truth. For the end of theoretical knowledge is truth, while
that of practical knowledge is action (for even if they consider
how things are, practical men do not study the eternal, but what
is relative and in the present). Now we do not know a truth
without its cause; and a thing has a quality in a higher degree
than other things if in virtue of it the similar quality belongs
to the other things as well (e.g. fire is the hottest of things;
for it is the cause of the heat of all other things); so that
that causes derivative truths to be true is most true. Hence the
principles of eternal things must be always most true (for they
are not merely sometimes true, nor is there any cause of their
being, but they themselves are the cause of the being of other
things), so that as each thing is in respect of being, so is it
in respect of truth.
Part 2
But evidently there is a first principle, and the causes of
things are neither an infinite series nor infinitely various in
kind. For neither can one thing proceed from another, as from
matter, ad infinitum (e.g. flesh from earth, earth from air, air
from fire, and so on without stopping), nor can the sources of
movement form an endless series (man for instance being acted on
by air, air by the sun, the sun by Strife, and so on without
limit). Similarly the final causes cannot go on ad infinitum,—walking
being for the sake of health, this for the sake of happiness,
happiness for the sake of something else, and so one thing always
for the sake of another. And the case of the essence is similar.
For in the case of intermediates, which have a last term and a
term prior to them, the prior must be the cause of the later
terms. For if we had to say which of the three is the cause, we
should say the first; surely not the last, for the final term is
the cause of none; nor even the intermediate, for it is the cause
only of one. (It makes no difference whether there is one
intermediate or more, nor whether they are infinite or finite in
number.) But of series which are infinite in this way, and of the
infinite in general, all the parts down to that now present are
alike intermediates; so that if there is no first there is no
cause at all.
Nor can there be an infinite process downwards, with a
beginning in the upward direction, so that water should proceed
from fire, earth from water, and so always some other kind should
be produced. For one thing comes from another in two ways—not in
the sense in which 'from' means 'after' (as we say 'from the
Isthmian games come the Olympian'), but either (i) as the man
comes from the boy, by the boy's changing, or (ii) as air comes
from water. By 'as the man comes from the boy' we mean 'as that
which has come to be from that which is coming to be' or 'as that
which is finished from that which is being achieved' (for as
becoming is between being and not being, so that which is
becoming is always between that which is and that which is not;
for the learner is a man of science in the making, and this is
what is meant when we say that from a learner a man of science is
being made); on the other hand, coming from another thing as
water comes from air implies the destruction of the other thing.
This is why changes of the former kind are not reversible, and
the boy does not come from the man (for it is not that which
comes to be something that comes to be as a result of coming to
be, but that which exists after the coming to be; for it is thus
that the day, too, comes from the morning—in the sense that it
comes after the morning; which is the reason why the morning
cannot come from the day); but changes of the other kind are
reversible. But in both cases it is impossible that the number of
terms should be infinite. For terms of the former kind, being
intermediates, must have an end, and terms of the latter kind
change back into one another, for the destruction of either is
the generation of the other.
At the same time it is impossible that the first cause, being
eternal, should be destroyed; for since the process of becoming
is not infinite in the upward direction, that which is the first
thing by whose destruction something came to be must be non-eternal.
Further, the final cause is an end, and that sort of end which
is not for the sake of something else, but for whose sake
everything else is; so that if there is to be a last term of this
sort, the process will not be infinite; but if there is no such
term, there will be no final cause, but those who maintain the
infinite series eliminate the Good without knowing it (yet no one
would try to do anything if he were not going to come to a limit);
nor would there be reason in the world; the reasonable man, at
least, always acts for a purpose, and this is a limit; for the
end is a limit.
But the essence, also, cannot be reduced to another definition
which is fuller in expression. For the original definition is
always more of a definition, and not the later one; and in a
series in which the first term has not the required character,
the next has not it either. Further, those who speak thus destroy
science; for it is not possible to have this till one comes to
the unanalysable terms. And knowledge becomes impossible; for how
can one apprehend things that are infinite in this way? For this
is not like the case of the line, to whose divisibility there is
no stop, but which we cannot think if we do not make a stop (for
which reason one who is tracing the infinitely divisible line
cannot be counting the possibilities of section), but the whole
line also must be apprehended by something in us that does not
move from part to part.—Again, nothing infinite can exist; and if
it could, at least the notion of infinity is not infinite.
But if the kinds of causes had been infinite in number, then
also knowledge would have been impossible; for we think we know,
only when we have ascertained the causes, that but that which is
infinite by addition cannot be gone through in a finite time.
Part 3
The effect which lectures produce on a hearer depends on his
habits; for we demand the language we are accustomed to, and that
which is different from this seems not in keeping but somewhat
unintelligible and foreign because of its unwontedness. For it is
the customary that is intelligible. The force of habit is shown
by the laws, in which the legendary and childish elements prevail
over our knowledge about them, owing to habit. Thus some people
do not listen to a speaker unless he speaks mathematically,
others unless he gives instances, while others expect him to cite
a poet as witness. And some want to have everything done
accurately, while others are annoyed by accuracy, either because
they cannot follow the connexion of thought or because they
regard it as pettifoggery. For accuracy has something of this
character, so that as in trade so in argument some people think
it mean. Hence one must be already trained to know how to take
each sort of argument, since it is absurd to seek at the same
time knowledge and the way of attaining knowledge; and it is not
easy to get even one of the two.
The minute accuracy of mathematics is not to be demanded in
all cases, but only in the case of things which have no matter.
Hence method is not that of natural science; for presumably the
whole of nature has matter. Hence we must inquire first what
nature is: for thus we shall also see what natural science treats
of (and whether it belongs to one science or to more to
investigate the causes and the principles of things).